Maths and Physics #4: The Long Divorce
At the end of
World War II came the “long divorce” of physics and maths. Physicists
only worked with well-established maths; and mathematicians had no interest in
physics. Neither side looked to advances in the other field for new ideas or
seeds that might be relevant to their own fields. Why had this happened?
Part of the reason
was that mathematicians feared that their field was becoming a “ragtag of
unconnected ideas and results”. Kurt Godel’s theorems had struck a dagger at
the very heart of maths – maths seemed to be in tatters. Best for
mathematicians to decide how their field could proceed, they felt. Another
reason was that physicists found they were able to make progress with existing
maths. And lastly, applied physics was in vogue, esp. solid state physics. The
engineering mindset – approximations were acceptable as long as they worked –
was becoming the norm. This, of course, made theoreticians in both physics and
maths wary, uncomfortable and even contemptuous of such physics.
Even in pure
theory, methods like Feynman’s “mystified his (physics) colleagues as
much as it horrified mathematicians” – the way it handled infinities seemed
absurd, but it worked. Since it was easy to use and yielded perfect answers, it
spread quickly. As Freeman Dyson said:
“Mathematical
rigour was the last thing that Feynman was ever concerned about.”
Mathematicians
were (not surprisingly) not OK with brushing infinites under the carpet without
proper reasons or rigour.
Then, the two
fields began to un-divorce. An instance here, another there.
Yang and Mills
worked out a purely mathematical field theory inspired by the symmetries in
Maxwell’s equations – it came to be called the Yang-Mills gauge symmetry.
But some of its predictions on the behavior of massless particles made no
sense, at least not when it was proposed. Physicists were understandably
dismissive of such a theory. It would take over 2 decades for experiments to
show the theory was right after all, but until then, this seemed like yet
another all-maths-no-physics “theory”.
Roger Penrose made numerous inventive contributions to
both physics and maths. Like twistors. The concept was too complex for most
physicists, and it didn’t serve any particular need either. It was therefore
ignored. But Penrose persevered anyway – his enthusiasm and personality
helped. Not only twistors, he argued, there were other areas where physics and
maths needed to learn from each other.
Freeman Dyson advocated greater interactions between
physicists and mathematicians. Group theory from maths might be relevant
to physics, he said. As with Penrose, there weren’t too many takers, but
eventually Dyson was proved right on the use of group theory in physics.
The Weinberg-Salam
theory predicted the existence of three exceptional particles that mediate
the electroweak force. Not only had the particles not been found (when the
theory was proposed), the maths was plagued with infinities. Gerard ‘t Hooft
found a way to systematically remove the infinities and with that, physicists
were willing to “hunt” for the particles predicted by theory. And soon those
particles began to be detected.
Identical ideas began to crop up in theoretical physics
and pure maths. Was there a “pre-established harmony” between the two fields
after all?
The long divorce was finally coming to an end.
Comments
Post a Comment